Tuesday, April 13, 2010

Reasoning Cause and Effect

For my research presentation I plan to explore the plausibility of causal relations and especially their connection to biological evolution. I hope to examine the extent to which our understanding of cause and effect accurately reflect the nature of the universe. I intend to analyze the relationship between a cause and an effect to determine what, if anything, connects the two. In this way, I hope to gain a better insight into both the process of the universe and my own mode of thinking.

Bergson criticizes both teleology and mechanism because they inevitably conclude, “All is given.” If every cause can be traced to its effects or every effect traced to its causes then the entirety of the universe could be predetermined given sufficient information and the appropriate equations. If this were the case then time would be irrelevant because every effect would have essentially already happened. Bergson argues towards certain creative power in the world. He states, “this reality is undoubtedly creative, i.e. productive of effects in which it expands and transcends its own being” (52). The cause, while observable in the first place, refuses to reveal its consequences prematurely. The precise effect cannot be known until it has unfolded in time. Bergson continues, “These effects were therefore not given in it in advance, and so it could not take them for ends, although, when once produced, they admit of a rational interpretation” (ibid). Teleology breaks down, according to Bergson, because causes do not anticipate their effects. It is only after the effect has been observed that the causal relation may be analyzed.

Hume calls into question causal relation all together. In his opinion, “knowledge of this relation is not, in any instance, attained by reasonings a priori; but arises entirely from experience” (27). Causal relations are not known except by observation. Hume states that the explosive property of gunpowder, for instance, could never “be discovered a priori” (28). The distinction between observation and reasoning is crucial. One must first experience a cause and effect before one can reason the connection. Reason comes secondary to observation. Hume writes, “A stone or piece of metal raised into the air, and left without any support, immediately falls: but to consider the matter a priori, is there anything we discover in this situation which can beget the idea of a downward, rather than an upward, or any other motion, in the stone or metal?” (29). This demonstrates that the world is not based on reason, but rather reason is based on the world. Future effects cannot be predicted a priori but must be rooted in previous knowledge. Likewise, a novel effect presents itself unexpectedly, and it is only after the event that causal connections may be drawn.

This is perhaps most evident in the study of evolution. Bergson writes, “That the appearance of a vegetable or animal species is due to specific causes, nobody will gainsay. But this can only mean that if, after the fact, we could know these causes in detail, we could explain by them the form that has been produced; foreseeing the form is out of the question” (27). According to Bergson, evolution offers a creativity to which causes can be inferred but of which effects cannot be predicted. For this reason, evolution does not follow a mechanistic or finalistic system. Bergson offers a metaphor: “no one, not even the artist, could have foreseen exactly what the portrait would be, for to predict it would have been to produce it before it was produced—an absurd hypothesis which is its own refutation” (6-7).

Though intelligence produced the theory of evolution, intelligence is itself an evolutionary adaption. Like any other adaptation, such as the ability to fly, man’s exceptional intelligence has allowed him to exploit a niche in nature. If intelligence is considered in the context of evolution then it is no more than an adaptation to improve our survival. The perception of cause and effect stems from the intellect. It is here that we must determine to what degree this evolutionary adaptation accurately captures the nature of the world. We have already said that a pure reasoning of the world ungrounded in observation would not align itself with the world as it is observed. Hume writes, “When we reason a priori, and consider merely any object or cause, as it appears to the mind, independent of all observation, it never could suggest to us the notion of any distinct object, such as its effect; much less, show us the inseparable and inviolable connexion between them” (31). The relationship between cause and effect is essentially unknown to reason; reason can only observe the sequence and then attribute a connection.

The assumption that our perception of causes and effects accurately reflect the nature of the world has lead to the development of mechanical and teleological systems. However, we are the ones imposing causality on nature. When one observes an event in nature contrary to one’s understanding, one manipulates the evidence until it confines to reason. Hume states, “It is confessed, that the utmost effort of human reason is to reduce the principles, productive of natural phenomena, to a greater simplicity, and to resolve the many particular effects into a few general causes, by means of reasonings from analogy, experience, and observation” (30). We may find success in attributing causes to effects on a relative level, but this in no way implies the universality of a cause-effect based system. Hume continues, “But as to the causes of these general causes, we should in vain attempt their discovery; nor shall we ever be able to satisfy ourselves, by any particular explication of them” (ibid). I propose that causal relations are not an absolute necessity, but only a useful understanding developed by the intellect through observation.

Heidegger video

Hey all i found the video that prof. Grady showed in class very interesting so i found the first part of it on Youtube. Its really good and done by the BBC so if you want to watch it here is the link.

Food for Thought: It’s not as Corny as this Title

Food for Thought:

It’s not as Corny as this Title

In the “Science and Philosophy” section of Creative Evolution, Henri Bergson discusses the topic of “positive science”, or the use of our intellect to create and make inventions. In this section, he claims that the human intellect is “at home” with inert, inorganic matter. Matter of this type is easier to comprehend the “inner nature of the inert matter” (Bergson 195). But when “the intellect undertakes the study of life, it necessarily treats the living like the inert, applying the same forms to this new object, carrying over into this new field the same habits that have succeeded so well in the old” (195). Living things are unpredictable, therefore we can’t ever claim to know “the inner nature” of the being, lest have control over it. However, the intellect has a disposition for looking at everything as unmoving and knowable objects. It is accustomed to do so most in part due to the fact that it is more advantageous for us to do so.

Bergson describes another characteristic of the human intellect in the earlier section, “The Function of the Intellect”. In the first part of the section, Bergson explicitly states that the intellect’s first aim is at constructing. And staying true to the claim that the intellect is most comfortable with inert matter, he states that this “fabrication is exercised exclusively on inert matter, in this sense that ever if it makes use of organized material, it treats it as inert, without troubling about the life which animated it” (153). The illusion that we can understand and predict the actions of living objects, combined with human being’s natural tendency to treat “the whole of matter … as an immense piece of cloth in which we can cut out what we will and sew it together again as we please” (156), have resulted in some pretty incredible discoveries and inventions, but also resulted in some advancements where the intellect got out of hand.

This last fact becomes more interesting when the reader considers that not only is the intellect an “organ” produced by evolution, it can help direct the process of evolution. While this might all sound like a bunch metaphysical jargon, it has its application in the real life. In the face of an obesity epidemic and a rising number of other health concerns that are related to our diet, lately people have been asked to think about the food that they eat. Whether they find out through TV Shows, or books, like Jonathan Safran Foer’s Eating Animals and Fast Food Nation, or films like Supersize Me and Food, Inc., people are learning about what they are putting in to their bodies and for the most part, are not pleased. Most of the shock comes from the discovery of the nutritional value (or lack thereof) in the food, but many others are appalled by the cause of the abhorrent quality of the food, the means of production.

In today’s market, much of the food has been modified one way or another. In the assembly line-production, consumer driven economy that we live in, all companies are pushed to make products bigger and better in the half the time. This is not so much a problem when humans are contained to inert, unorganized matter, but when humans run into trying to apply these standards to living matter, they run into a problem. And this is exactly the situation human beings are in regarding their current practices of mass-producing food. Before this era of food awareness and activism, the question may have seemed obsolete, but knowing what we know now about the production of our food, philosophy has once again come to the forefront of “real life” situations, when we, as many have (even perhaps without knowing they have done so) ask: What is metaphysically wrong about the way that food is being produced?

The production of genetically modified food by human beings is a perfect example of how the intellect tends to treat organisms as inert, predictable beings and exemplifies its inclination to fabricate new things from organized matter, without “troubling about the life which animated it”. Furthermore, when one considers once again that the intellect is an organ of evolution, which is able to direct evolution, one can see the correlation of how our inclination to direct evolution in a way that is preferable to us, without “troubling the life which animated it” could lead to some big problems. This in part due to the fact that the “…intelligence which aims at fabricating is an intelligence which never stops at the actual form of things, nor regards it as final, but on the contrary looks upon all matter if it were carvable at will” (156).

But not all objects are knowable, predictable, or “carvable at will”. We have tried to create an organism that is molded to our will. We have dissected, studied, analyzed, experimented, and theorized features of living beings and in essence tried to turn know everything about the living organism to the point where we “know” that if we add a certain element into an organism’s developmental process or modify this or that gene, we can produce a certain outcome, or a specific organism. We have “understood” the being so well, that we claim to have established a form of predictability in the objects that we have produced.

This desire for predictability, or longing for repetition is one of the other salient features of the intellect as described by Bergson. Much like the other features of the intellect, it has made its way from dealing only with inert objects to transferring its logic on to living organisms also. Scientists have successfully attempted to modify genes in a way that tomatoes grow bigger and redder, apples are hardier and taste sweeter and chickens that are meatier and mature in half the time. They have experimented to the point that they can predict that, when they change a certain element in one generation, it will have an effect in the future generations.

In essence they have attempted to create a perfect predictability, or finalism for the organism they are affecting. But, as Bergson says, we can never truly can predict the future, but furthermore, he claims that we try to modify organisms, without “troubling the life which animated it”. In a typical human manner, we placed ourselves in the focal point, and percieved that everything was suited for our ends, without thought to the greater good. If this is taken for true, than everything is an abomination, because we have actually changed the way that other things live. We not only alter the organisms individual life, but we alter life and the drive for evolution as a whole.

The one feature that causes life and evolution to continue on is the open-endedness of it all. There is no master plan, or final goal that life is striving for. But, by inserting ourselves in the course of evolution and altering life as we see fit, we could end up doing something highly-disadvantageous for the human race as a whole. We seek to cap the open-endedness of life and evolution without understanding, or even having the ability to understand it. If we try to control all aspects of life and evolution, and no check is put on our intellect, we may find ourselves once again in a society that accepts eugenics or ethnic cleansing.

For this paper, I will be focusing mainly on Bergson, put referencing other authors covered in the class where the information is relative. For my research I will be watching Food Inc, and reading Fast Food Nation and Eating Animals. I also intend to use Human Genome Project’s website for any technical or scientific information.

Sunday, April 11, 2010

Natural Laws

Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy concerned primarily with investigating the nature of being. One of the most significant ideas metaphysics explores is movement, a theme that appears throughout the work of many distinguished philosophers. Many philosophers believe that causality, which examines the relationship between an event and its effect, plays an important role in analyzing the movement between natural beings. Aristotle introduces the idea of the “first mover,” who is responsible for setting all things in motion. The first mover comprehends the whole of being and cannot be influenced by any material being. Like traditional metaphysics, theology places the laws that govern nature outside of the material realm. Reality is found beyond the natural world, in what is eternal and unchangeable. Although theologians are able to integrate supernatural ideas into Aristotle’s metaphysics, this task proves more difficult with the ideas of Henri Bergson. Bergson believes that the laws that govern nature develop within nature, which is in a constant state of change. These contrasting ideas present a controversial topic within metaphysics. Should the laws of nature be included in the supernatural realm, or within the material world? Immanuel Kant, who tends to ground his philosophy in experience, seems to offer a solution to this controversial topic.
In Religion within the Limits of Reason Alone, Kant explains that rational beings are inclined to promote the highest moral good (89). The “morally, well-disposed” man, however, faces a constant attack from the evil principle, which restricts his ability to perform ethical actions (85). The ultimate goal of the individual is to resist this evil and break free from the laws of sin. Kant believes that individuals are not evil by nature, rather, they are immoral only through their interaction with other members of society. Despite the good will of each individual, men make one another evil by corrupting each other’s moral predisposition (88). As a result, an individual that associates with others runs the risk of straying away from the good. Kant explains that, in order to obtain the highest moral good, individuals must form an alliance designed to further the good and protect man from the evil principle. The good principle is achievable through the creation of a society that is responsible for spreading moral laws throughout humanity. If mankind fails to create a society that aims “solely at the maintenance of morality,” then it will fall into the hands of evil (86).
Kant believes that humanity has the potential to become united under an “ethical commonwealth,” which consists of a union of men guided exclusively by laws of virtue (87). Unlike the members of a political state, who are subject to an external authority, the members of an ethical commonwealth have the power to advocate their own law. Although an ethical commonwealth is grounded in laws that are non-coercive, it may choose to accept a constitution based on public law. In order to be “ethical,” however, the laws of a commonwealth cannot be determined by its members. Public human laws are directed toward the legality of actions, rather than their inner morality (90). Kant believes that the concept of an ethical commonwealth can be extended to the whole of mankind because the duties of virtue apply to all human beings (88). He explains that an ethical society strives to attain harmony with all men by encouraging moral action. As members of this community, however, individuals are unable to overcome the forces that separate mankind and require something greater than themselves to help them establish a universal republic (90).
The establishment of a universal church involves a special combination of ecclesiastical faith and pure religious faith. Kant explains that the constitution of every church originates in ecclesiastical faith. “Ecclesiastical faith,” or historical faith, is dependent upon the conditions of experience (96). Although ecclesiastical faith is grounded in fact, it is subject to the circumstances of time or place and dependent on man’s ability to accurately judge certain situations. “Pure religious faith,” on the other hand, is a ”rational” faith that can be believed in and shared by everyone (94). Because rational beings understand their incapacity to understand the supersensible, a faith pertaining strictly to what is available through intuition is appealing to the senses. A church, however, must entertain the idea that its organization is a divine arrangement that is completely harmonious with moral religion (96). Similarly, human nature prevents the establishment of a church based on pure faith alone. In contrast to the faith established in tradition, the faith that is grounded in scripture endures through all objections and provides a pure doctrine of religion (98).
The idea that individuals are insufficient both in their inability to establish moral laws and unite mankind leads to the idea of a higher moral being who assists mankind with these tasks. This being is the one who “knows the heart” and is able to sense the personal temperament of each individual (91). Ethical laws originate from the will of this being, which determine the worth of human action. Kant explains that the divine, legislative will commands through purely moral laws (90). While the laws concerning the legality of actions serve as the means to spread religion, pure moral legislation constitutes all true religion (95). Kant believes that mankind should only be concerned with the ideas that are presented in a practical context. Kant believes that practical reason can morally comprehend the idea of god as the “holy Legislator,” “moral Guardian,” and “righteous Judge” (131). Human reason can understand the notion of god through these characteristics because it presents the moral relation of god to mankind. This description of god can be presented to human reason everywhere and is practical for the development of an ethical commonwealth.
Kant describes god as the “highest lawgiver of an ethical commonwealth” (90). Therefore, the people of an ethical commonwealth are considered a people of god. Kant explains that the organization of a people of god can only be realized in the form of a church. A “church visible,” in particular, is the actual union of men into a whole under “divine world-government” (92). The purpose of the church is grounded within the material realm. It is the responsibility of mankind to “exhibit the kingdom of God on earth” (92). The union of the church must be motivated by moral forces and the members of the church must be free from political authority. The members of a “true” church must also administer basic laws and principles that are consistent and unchangeable (93). Kant further explains that God is honored and glorified through an individual’s participation in a good course of life (96). Because it is impossible for man to have any influence on god, individuals must direct their actions towards mankind. An individual is “perpetually in the service of God” when they fulfill their duties to themselves and others (94).
Kant offers a solution to the controversy concerning where the laws that govern nature should be placed in the study of being. Kant explains that society, or an individual’s interaction with other men, naturally makes that individual corrupt and evil. He encourages humanity to strive to obtain the good, which can only be accomplished under an ethical commonwealth. In this type of society, a supreme being uses moral laws to direct mankind. An ethical commonwealth is dependent upon this holy legislator, who expresses his divine will through these laws and determines the “goodness” of human action. Kant further explains the significance of having faith in both the church and this higher moral being. An intimate connection between these two faiths is necessary for the establishment of a universal church. Kant, however, believes that these laws are only beneficial for creating a moral and virtuous society. Divine commandments are only significant if they are used to achieve ethical ends. Kant explains that an individual’s “service” to god involves fulfilling his duties toward other men. Because mankind can only influence what is found in the natural world, an individual must avoid acting for the supernatural. Similarly, in order for the laws of nature to have any influence on mankind, they must be located within the material realm.

Thursday, April 8, 2010

Ethics and Metaphysics

Within Kierkegaard’s Fear and Trembling, there seems to be two aspects of metaphysics that are being called into questioned. First, there is the idea of the three different realms and the type of world these three spheres are situated within and the experiences they create. These realms are in a specific context, which develops the metaphysical ideas of the type of nature where human beings live. In conjunction, Kierkegaard’s work calls into question the metaphysics as a singular form of experience as a being. To fully understand “being qua being” in the world, Kierkegaard suggests that one must look at the metaphysics in conjunction with the ethics. Metaphysics and ethics are inseparable when trying to understand humans in the world. Searching for the metaphysical questions that we have been discussing in class such as what it means to be, how it varies in form, and studying what is cannot be fully explored or understood without considering the ethics. For Kierkegaard, metaphysics and ethics cannot be drawn out as singular matters to consider, but rather they should be seen in correlation to one another. In support, I will be reviewing Kant’s third antinomy. There are four antinomies where he considers two contrasting ideas. He accounts for their differences, but is able to connect them in some regard. The third antinomy is the one of most importance for my thesis. It discusses nature and freedom, which parallels my ideas of metaphysics and ethics. Also in support, an article in International Journal of Ethics titled Ethics and Metaphysics is written by Dorothy Walsh who attempts to show not only that “ethics… has its metaphysical presuppositions.” It is not only a matter of considering them as being connected, but she seems to question how much ethics depends on metaphysics.

My first primary source is Kierkegaard’s Fear and Trembling. As discussed, the first metaphysical aspect called into question is the nature of the environment in which we live. The study of what is revolves around the type of environment that we are placed within. (This is the first step in recognizing the connection between metaphysics and ethics.) There are three realms according to Kierkegaard that we exist in the world. First, there is the aesthetic realm. This deals with individual relationships on a personal level such as an inside joke or a common understanding in a relationship. The next realm is the ethical, which holds universal understanding such as judgments, rules and laws. The final realm is the religious, which is an actual relationship with God. Kierkegaard uses these realms to identify the Biblical relationship between Abraham and God. In the story, God calls upon Abraham to sacrifice his one and only son. Having faith in the Lord, Abraham obeys what the Lord has asked and takes Isaac to the top of the mountain to be sacrificed. This act has been used by many scholars as a reference to absolute faith, which is taking the “what is” of the situation and calling it into question due to the lack of understanding of the world. Normally, we perceive things through the universal, even our relationship with God. Kierkegaard wants to ask the question of whether the universal can be completely overlooked and there can be a direct relationship with God. This would alter our general understanding of the world, and it would seem that to do this would correlate not only to the way of acting in the world, but how and why one acts in the world drawing on the ethics of the situation. To clarify, the ethics are a large part of being in the world when we look at the story not as mere facts, but the truth of the situation. Kierkegaard asks how this can be a true testament of faith, when ethically it is so wrong. The perspective of the world and the moral duties of a father and of a religious leader of God seem to encompass both metaphysical questions and ethical questions.

My next source will be Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, where he attempts to settle the question of freedom verse the idea that everything is determined by nature. He goes on to define the what he means by freedom and nature. He says that the laws of nature are only significant in space and time; therefore, they are valid in their appearance. Freedom is existing outside the confines of experiences; therefore, they only apply to things within themselves. Yet, the overarching theme appears that reason excludes the idea of experience. There is a more indepth analysis which will be covered in my paper, but essentially Kant gets to the point that humans can be free and can also be subjected to the confinements of the natural world. His analysis is another attempt to show that freedom, an ethical question, is inseparable from the metaphysical question such as the laws of nature.

Another one of my sources comes from the International Journal of Ethics. Dorthy Walsh writes on Ethics and Metaphysics. She does not question whether or not they are used in conjunction, but rather how much they overlap. Her question is along the lines of how much of ethical questions are reliant upon metaphysics. There seems to be a dependency of ethics and this could create a whole new form of inquiry. So many times, philosophers try to separate these questions into epistemological, logical, metaphysical, when in reality by taking them out of the realm of the whole they miss a large part of the experience or knowledge they are trying to gain. It is through this paper that I am going to attempt to show the importance of keeping an open mind when studying the philosophical questions. Although it is convenient to analyze one aspect at a time, it significantly alters how something should b perceived in reality. Through Kierkegaard’s example of Abraham and God situated within the different realms and supported by many other philosophers work, I will attempt to show that the ethics and metaphysics are inseparable when analyzing these forms of knowledge.

Wednesday, April 7, 2010

Kant's "Nature" and Apriori Rules of Morality

While Aristotle would posit that humans and human sensibility are necessarily in harmony with the natural world, as it exists in actuality, Kant would argue to the contrary claiming we can have no “true” knowledge of objects in and of themselves. Kant asserts that the apriori formal conditions of our knowledge, namely space and time, allow us to intuit only those objects that conform to these apriori conditions. However, despite the fact that we can only intuit “representations” we nonetheless know that something must be responsible for the representation, namely the object in and of itself, so that our existence can still be considered as grounded in an objective reality. Accordingly, we too are subject to the apriori universal laws of nature that govern the sensible world. While our sensible intuitions and representations of the understanding must remain grounded in actual experience, as humans, and therefore rational beings, we are also endowed with the faculty of reason. In the final sections of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, he shows the tendency of reason to always seek the unconditioned. However, because we can never sensibly intuit the unconditioned, reason by its very nature continually attempts to overstep its limitations.  This is highlighted in the third antimony that shows how reason, when overstepping its limits, can lead to two contradictory conclusions. On the one hand, human freedom is necessary in regards to moral responsibility, but thereby creates a “lawlessness” and disunity of experience as it breaks the tie between cause and effect by allowing for spontaneity. On the other hand, if the universal laws of nature are all that govern the universe, there becomes an issue of infinite regress towards the unconditioned, something that reason by its very nature tends towards but can have no validated experience of.

While Kant leaves us at this seemingly irreconcilable divide between human freedom and the mechanistic laws of nature in his Critique of Pure Reason, he picks this concept back up in his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and subsequently argues that the concept of morality can be found apriori in the faculty of reason.

Within his argument the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals he divides beings into two groups, non-rational and rational. He then defines human beings as a subset of rational beings that are a part of the intelligible world, but also necessarily tied to the sensible world. It is this dualistic nature that allows us to act freely and autonomously with regards to the intelligible world yet still be bound to the determinate laws of nature which govern our sensible world. Furthermore, because we are creatures of the sensible world we have desires, inclinations and sensations that oftentimes influence our actions, of which we freely choose. However, actions made solely for satisfying some desire or inclination of our own are not moral. Morality is defined as a duty of rational beings to act “as if the maxim of your action were to become by your will a universal law of nature” (Groundwork, p. 31) and “act that you use your humanity, whether in your own person or in the person of any other, always at the same time as an end, never merely as a means” (Groundwaork, p. 38). So that one must first consider if one’s actions could be viewed as universally applicable and second, assure oneself that humanity is not being used as a means of achieving one’s goal. This is because to use another person would be to encroach upon their autonomy and would therefore undermine the value of your own autonomy and human freedom in general.

Kant’s discussion of the tension between efficient causes of the natural world on sensible beings and the necessity of human freedom for autonomous rational beings raises many questions:

How is “nature” defined and what is our relation to it? Is there a distinction between the natural world and human nature (humanity)? If so, what is human nature? How does the presupposition of our relation to nature necessarily affect any metaphysical argument? How is the sensible world different from the intelligible world? What is the status given to the idea of autonomy and independence within the field of metaphysics generally? If we are a part of the natural world, are we ascribed a particular status in relation to other objects?

In regards to Kant’s delineation of “non-rational” and “rational” beings, an article by Allen Wood focuses on the ethical concerns of the treatment of non-rational beings. In other words, according to Kant’s argument, are we required to treat animals and nature as a whole with respect or, as seems the case, can we use them indiscriminately as means for achieving our own ends? Wood argues that the central problem is “Kant regards only rational beings as persons, which are not to be treated as ends, regarding all other beings as things” (Wood, 193). However, Wood believes Kant’s principles which require a duty of humans to respect humanity “as the ultimate end of nature” implicitly require that “we undertake the responsibility of shaping our ends in such a way that hey provide this system [ecosystem] with its […] harmony”(Wood, p. 204). In short, Wood is skeptical of the implications Kant’s Formula of Humanity could have, namely rational beings could merely use nature as they please, but ultimately believes Kant’s arguments, when taken as a whole, support efforts to preserve the natural world.

While the previous article analyzes the relationship between non-rational and rational beings, Michael Nelson’s article focuses on the interpersonal relationships of rational beings as a group. In attempts to better understand the actual ways in which Kant’s Formula of Humanity could be implemented socially, Nelson looks to Kant’s Formula of Autonomy and Formula of the Kingdom of Ends. Nelson proposes that because “rational agents can coordinate plans both intrapersonally and interpersonally” that Kant is really keying in on an “idea of social cooperation […] flexible enough to allow a variety of different, specific realizations” (Nelson, p. 105).  In short, Nelson argues that it is not simply enough to value humans because they can, as autonomous beings, generate their own ends, but more importantly these ends under social and political contracts can be harmonized and mutually beneficial. Kant’s morality as interpreted by Nelson, “requires an ongoing process of give-and-take, mutual adjustment”( Nelson, p. 101).  I would argue, however, against Nelson’s argument as I believe Kant would not refer to the laws of morality as a “process of give-and-take” to be adjusted relative to the individuals in question. Morality as viewed by Kant is a set of ahistorical, apriori rules necessitated by our faculty of reason (or more importantly the reason of any rational being). For humans, who must operate in both the sensible and intelligible world, the Kingdom of Ends is a mere ideal as the human race can never be expected to follow the categorical imperatives of morality as a necessary set of rules. We as a autonomous beings have choices and are influenced not only by moral duty, but also by sensible desires and the two cannot be simultaneously fulfilled at all times. 

The other secondary sources to be used address the Kantian relationship between reason, morality, freedom. These articles “Morality and Freedom: Kant’s Reciprocity Thesis”, “Kant’s Anti-determinism” and “The Value of Reason and the Value of Freedom”, all offer analysis of the seemingly paradoxical idea that it is within our autonomous freedom that we discover the apriori laws of morality. In brief, Kant’s argument follows that if we have reason, we must suppose ourselves to be self-causing and therefore “free” and autonomous. However, if we believe ourselves to be autonomous it none-the-less follows that we must accept the autonomy of all other rational beings. Therefore, we are morally obligated to respect humanity as an end (self-determining) and never as a means so that dignity is only achieved when we act in ways that would be deemed universally applicable.      

While the main thesis is not yet refined, the central focus of the paper will be to elaborate on the concept of “nature” in reference to both the efficient laws of nature of which we are bound by the sensible world as well as the laws of morality of which we are bound by the intelligible world. Furthermore to fully understand Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, it is important to elaborate on his division of non-rational and rational beings as well as his differentiation of a purely rational being and a human being.

 

Duration

Henri Bergson begins the first chapter of his book Creative Evolution with a reflection on time and how individuals perceive it. He asserts that the way science looks at time as a series of individual moments that are possible to differentiate is wrong. Bergson believes this because experiences build upon each other and no two instances are exactly alike. Instead Bergson would have individuals perceive time as states that move from one to the next continuously, each state building upon all the other states that preceded it. Why do we describe time and change in this abstract and, in Bergson’s opinion, incorrect manner? If Bergson is correct then our understanding of the world around us and how we perceive things may have to change.
When describing how things change, people generally indicate points on a timeline at and identify them as when something became something else; this is especially true of evolution. Scientists identify points in time and define what the organism was then. Organisms are said to be one thing at this time and then become another at that time. Bergson points out is that the problem with this method is that these organisms didn’t just become these new species all of a sudden, as it might suggest. Instead things change gradually over time, slowly changing from one form to the next. A fish did not just wake up one day and become able to survive on land, instead each generation of fish changed slightly from the one before it. Every generation built upon the growth of its ancestors, the progeny consistently overcoming the parents.
Our lifetimes can be perceived a similar way. If one reflects on themselves as a child, one can instantly see how he is different now than he was then. While we are different than we were previously, we are undeniably still the same person throughout our lifetimes. So is there an identifiable point at which each one of became the man or woman we are today? Certainly not; we would instead say that we gradually grew and changed to become the person we are today. As organisms there is no stop to our change. We change continuously at the same rate, each moment we experience building upon the last, our intellect revising as necessary according to new information. This continual change is what Bergson describes as duration.
Duration is not just the replacing of each instant with the next. Nothing is being replaced and everything continues to have an effect. Each moment is influenced by the one that preceded it such that each moment builds upon what every moment that preceded it started. Bergson describes duration excellently as “…the continuous progress of the past which gnaws into the future and which swells as it advances” (4). This description brings to mind the idea of the “snowball effect”. Each moment that passes is added onto our snowball of experience and influences every moment that follows.
Understanding the past might inform our actions in the present, but an experience can never be repeated twice even with the same conditions present, and as such it is impossible to foretell the future. Since each experience builds upon all the ones that preceded it, even if we are presented with the same circumstances of an experience a second time, we will not have the same experience as our previous experience of the same circumstance because the first one informs the new one. As such, even if we could possibly know all the variables in the equation of experience, we would still not know what will come. Bergson describes this occurrence by relating it to the painting of a portrait: even if one know what the model, background, canvas, paints and brush look like, no one, not even the painter himself , can possibly know how the portrait will turn out. To foretell the future is to try and indentify what we have not experienced by way of what we have already experienced, which are necessarily different.
Bergson ends his section on duration with a thought on existence: “…we find that, for a conscious being, to exist is to change, to change is to mature, to mature is to go on creating oneself endlessly. Should the same be said of existence in general?” (7). When we exist, we take part in duration necessarily, which means we are constantly changing. What changes us are new experiences that inform our understanding and improve our abilities. As such, to change is to mature. As we mature we recreate ourselves better than before. Bergson ends by asking us whether we can describe existence as this progress, and it appears we can.
If Bergson is correct and we start looking at our own existence in this fashion, it appears we have only to gain from it. Instead of constantly living in the present, individuals would look to the past to inform their present actions. This act can only make the future of one’s existence better. If we keep in mind that every experience builds upon the ones that preceded it then we will make sure to do the best we can with every experience. The reason we gain from this practice is that our futures can only get better if we improve our pasts.
As was previously described, our experiences of the past are constantly trying to overflow into our present. What is meant by that is our past cannot be stopped from influencing our present actions. Our past experiences are preserved in how they influence our later experiences. Therefore every experience informs our mental capacity and improves our means. If we make sure to have informative experiences as often as possible, then just as the past pushes into the present, our new improved intellects will inform our present without effort.
If we are to take up Bergson’s ideas on duration and how we experience, then we will be forced to change how we consider experience and education. This is not a bad thing though, as it should surely improve how we grow and improve our intellects and abilities. However it seems a difficult task to drastically change how we perceive the world.